âinvention,â and the Malthusian âstruggle for existence.â It is Hobbesâ bellum omnium contra omnes (the war of all against all).
Yet Marx was a great admirer of Darwinâand in this apparent paradox lies resolution. For reasons involving all the themes I have emphasized hereâthat inductivism is inadequate, that creativity demands breadth, and that analogy is a profound source of insightâgreat thinkers cannot be divorced from their social background. But the source of an idea is one thing; its truth or fruitfulness is another. The psychology and utility of discovery are very different subjects indeed. Darwin may have cribbed the idea of natural selection from economics, but it may still be right. As the German socialist Karl Kautsky wrote in 1902: âThe fact that an idea emanates from a particular class, or accords with their interests, of course proves nothing as to its truth or falsity.â In this case, it is ironic that Adam Smithâs system of laissez faire does not work in his own domain of economics, for it leads to oligopoly and revolution, rather than to order and harmony. Struggle among individuals does, however, seem to be the law of nature.
Many people use such arguments about social context to ascribe great insights primarily to the indefinable phenomenon of good luck. Thus, Darwin was lucky to be born rich, lucky to be on the Beagle , lucky to live amidst the ideas of his age, lucky to trip over Parson Malthusâessentially little more than a man in the right place at the right time. Yet, when we read of his personal struggle to understand, the breadth of his concerns and study, and the directedness of his search for a mechanism of evolution, we understand why Pasteur made his famous quip that fortune favors the prepared mind.
6 | Death Before Birth, or a Miteâs Nunc Dimittis
CAN ANYTHING BE more demoralizing than parental incompetence before the most obvious and innocent of childrenâs questions: why is the sky blue, the grass green? Why does the moon have phases? Our embarrassment is all the more acute because we thought we knew the answer perfectly well, but hadnât rehearsed it since we ourselves had received a bumbled response in similar circumstances a generation earlier. It is the things we think we knowâbecause they are so elementary, or because they surround usâthat often present the greatest difficulties when we are actually challenged to explain them.
One such question, with an obvious and incorrect answer, lies close to our biological lives: why, in humans (and in most species familiar to us), are males and females produced in approximately equal numbers? (Actually, males are more common than females at birth in humans, but differential mortality of males leads to a female majority in later life. Still, the departures from a one to one ratio are never great.) At first glance, the answer seems to be, as in Rabelaisâs motto, âplain as the nose on a manâs face.â After all, sexual reproduction requires a mate; equal numbers imply universal matingâthe happy Darwinian status of maximal reproductive capacity. At second glance, it isnât so clear at all, and we are drawn in confusion to Shakespeareâs recasting of the simile: âA jest unseen, inscrutable, invisible, as a nose on a manâs face.â If maximal reproductive capacity is the optimal state for a species, then why make equal numbers of males and females. Females, after all, set the limit upon numbers of offspring, since eggs are invariably so much larger and less abundant than sperm in species familiar to usâthat is, each egg can make an offspring, each sperm cannot. A male can impregnate several females. If a male can mate with nine females and the population contains a hundred individuals, why not make ten males and ninety females? Reproductive capacity will certainly exceed that of a population composed of fifty males and