original Talibanâs success at taking power in 1994â6. Whether this scenario will be repeated is perhaps a âknown unknownâ.
Strategic thought tends to reject the idea that âgang warfareâ is really war. Gangs and criminals use force for direct advantage rather than within a mechanism that provides a military decision on which a political outcome is based. This is political advantage in the broad sense of an adjustment of circumstances in oneâs favour, as opposed to just describing competition for state offices. Yet this is close to the way in which force is used by many actors in the war in Afghanistan, although it does not make the use of violence any less lethal.
In the Clausewitzian paradigm of war, the enemy is coerced into subscription to oneâs strategic narrative: he dies, or becomes no longer relevant. This makes the translation of force into political meaning relatively simple. Even if the enemy utilises a different interpretive structure, one can ultimately force an outcome upon him. While armed conflict continues to be at its core a clash of organised violence, the Clausewitzian notion that attack is the âpositiveâ and defence the ânegativeâ component of translating force into political meaning, a warâs âdecisionâ, is compromised in Afghanistan. Ultimately the more fragmented a political environment, the more actions are interpreted individually in directly political terms rather than as part of the military balance in the scale of a conflictâs military outcome. The proliferation of strategic audiences beyond the enemy means that force no longer has a clear target: one cannot âforceâ an outcome on a strategic audience that is not the enemy; they may well be free to ignore the warâs military outcome.
The effect of violence in fragmented political environments
Clausewitz saw three elements at play in war: policy, passion and warâs uncertain dynamics, âthe play of chance and probabilityâ. He referred to this as the âtrinityâ of war, in that these three elements formed the âoneâ, which was war. These three elements of war were for Clausewitz representedin his conception of the state at war. Reason (or policy) was represented by the government (bearing in mind that Clausewitzâs Prussia was a monarchy) and passion by the people. The army did not strictly represent warâs dynamics, but was the component of the state that had to confront the uncertainty inherent in combat. 22
The nature of war was for Clausewitz constant, even though its character evolved. By situating warâs nature in terms of the interaction of three variables, his definition remains flexible. While the Afghan conflict is not war in an inter-state sense, its basic nature can still be comprehended in terms of an interaction of these three elements. However, unlike in conventional inter-state war (in which policy tends to be the dominant characteristic), as there are a multitude of political actors, the role of human passion, and the unpredictable, potentially explosive, dynamics of violent clash, increasingly infrom the conflictâs basic definition.
The consequence of the use of violence in war is often that fighting generates an antagonism of its own that distances people from their political common ground. Clausewitz acknowledged this: âeven where there is no national hatred and no animosity to start with, the fighting itself will stir up hostile feelingsâ. 23 Clausewitz understood violence to be an explosive, reciprocal force. The idea that âviolence begets violenceâ has always been part of human conflict; as Tacitus put it: âonce killing starts, it is difficult to draw the lineâ. 24 However, while the Clausewitzian paradigm recognises that violence may accentuate, or entirely generate, emotional antagonism, that antagonism is delimited by the strategic audiencesâ location